Deinde considerandum est de divisione inter
gentem (vel nationem) et civitatem secundum beatum Thomam de Aquino. Circa
hoc quaeritur: utrum gens vel natio est causa materialis communitatis
politicae?
|
We must now consider the division between nation
and state according to St Thomas Aquinas. Under this heading it is asked: whether
the nation is the material cause of the political community?
|
Et sic proceditur. Videtur quod beatus Thomas
haud dividit gentem ex civitate tamquam causa ex effectu, immo non dividit
essentialiter gentem ex civitate. Quia dicitur (1a 2ae q.95 a.4) quod ius
positivum dividitur in ius gentium et ius civile, id est ius civitatis. Sed
ius gentium non definit ut ius proprium singularum gentium vel nationum; sed ius
quod “omnes fere gentes utuntur” (ibid., obj. 1; cf. Isid. Etym. 5.6; Grat.
Decr. D.1 c.9). Patet enim quia, secundum beatum Thomam et Isidorum et
Gratianum quoque, ius gentium est ius quasi universale servatum in universo
orbi terrarum. Atqui gens (vel natio) non est aliquid universale, sed
distinguitur gens una ex gente altera sicut unus homo ex altero. Ergo divisio
gentis ex civitate non congruit divisioni iuris gentium ex iure civili
secundum beatum Thomam.
|
Objection 1: It would seem that St
Thomas does not at all divide nation from state as cause from effect, nor
does he even make any essential division of nation from state. For it is said
(1a 2ae q.95 a.4) that positive law is divided into law of
nations and civil law, that is, the law of a state. But he does not define
the law of nations as a law which belongs to individual nations; but as the law
which “nearly all nations use” (ibid., obj. 1; cf. Isid. Etym. 5.6; Grat. Decr. D.1 c.9). For it is evident that,
according to St Thomas and Isidore and Gratian as well, the law of nations is
a sort of universal law observed all over the world. A nation, however, is
not something universal, but one nation is distinct from another nation just
as one man is distinct from another. Therefore, according to St Thomas
Aquinas, the distinction between nation and state does not correspond to the
distinction between law of nations and civil law.
|
Praeterea, si gens vel natio esset distincta
essentialiter ex civitate, ius gentium esset ius non factum a civitatibus,
sed gentibus. Sed in D.1 c.9 Isidorus dicit: “Ius gentium est sedium
occupatio, edificatio, munitio, bella, captivitates, servitutes, postliminia,
federa pacis, induciae, legatorum non violandorum religio, conubia inter
alienigenas prohibita” (Isid. Etym.
5.6). Sed federa et induciae fiunt a civitatibus, vel proprie ab
civitatis auctoritatibus pro civitate. Inde ius gentium, quod haec civilia
continet, est ius a civitatibus factum. Ergo gens non dividitur essentialiter
ex civitate apud beatum Thomam, quoniam beatus Thomas, Isidorum secutus,
verbum gentes utitur pro civitatibus.
|
Objection 2: Moreover, if the nation was
essentially distinct from the state, the law of nations would be a law made
not by states but by nations. But in D.1 c.9 (trans. Thompson and Gordley) Isidore says: “The law of nations deals with
occupation of habitations, with building, fortification, war, captivity,
servitude, postliminy, treaties, armistices, truces, the obligation of not
harming ambassadors, and the prohibition of marriage with aliens” (Isid. Etym. 5.6). But treaties
and armistices are made by states, or more properly by governing authorities
on behalf of a state. Hence the law of nations, which deals with these
matters of state, is a law made by states. Therefore nation is not
essentially divided from state in St Thomas, since St Thomas, following
Isidore, uses the word ‘nations’ for ‘states.’
|
Sed contra est quod Dominus dicit Abrahae in
libro Genes. (12:2): Faciamque te in gentem magnam.
|
On the contrary, the Lord says to Abraham in
Genesis (12:2): And I will make of thee a great nation.
|
Respondeo dicendum quod, communitas politica vel
civitas habet quattuor causas, scilicet causam efficientem formalem finalem
et materialem.
|
I answer that, the political community or
state has four causes, namely an efficient, formal, final, and material
cause.
|
Unde causa efficiens civitatis est auctoritas:
aut delegatio vel acceptio auctoritatis a populo, aut tributio auctoritatis a
Deo, aut alius actus conferens vel praeponens vel designans unum agentem
auctoritatem populo.
|
And so the efficient cause of the state is an
authority: either the delegation or acceptance of an authority by the people,
or the assignment of authority by God, or some other action conferring or setting
up or marking out one agent as the authority for a people.
|
Causa formalis civitatis est regimen: ut beatus
Thomas dicit (1a 2ae q.95 a.4), Aristotelem secutus, sunt “diversa regimina
civitatum,” scilicet regnum, aristocratia regimen, populi regimen.
|
The formal cause of the state is the regime: as
St Thomas says (1a 2ae q.95 a.4), following Aristotle, there are “various forms
of government,” namely monarchy, aristocracy, democracy.
|
Causa finalis civitatis est cooperatio multorum
hominum ad persequendum bonum commune vel bona coniunctim. Ergo, causa
efficiens civitatis dicitur alio modo consensus populi ad persequendum bonum
commune sub aliqua auctoritate.
|
The final cause of the state is the cooperation
of many men in the pursuit of a common good or of several good things
together. Therefore, the efficient cause of the state is, to speak in another
way, the agreement of a people to pursue the common good under a certain
authority.
|
Causa materialis civitatis est gens vel natio,
sed non exclusive. Possunt enim coniungi aliae hominum congregationes in
regimine sub auctoritate ad persequendum bonum commune tamquam civitas; ut urbs,
regnum, imperium sunt varia civitatis genera, etenim ecclesia est quasi
civitas vel communitas politica. Unde gens vel natio est civitatis una
possibilis materia, sed non excluditur alia materia; et omnis materia
civitatis comprehenditur in verbo ‘populus,’ ut habet beatus Thomas (1a 2ae
q.105 a.3) cum dicit: “si statim extranei advenientes reciperentur ad
tractandum ea quae sunt populi, possent multa pericula contingere; dum
extranei, non habentes adhuc amorem firmatum ad bonum publicum, aliqua contra
populum attentarent.” Ergo causa materialis civitatis proprie est populus.
|
The material cause of the state is the nation,
but not exclusively. For other kinds of social group can be joined together
into a regime under an authority to pursue a common good as a state; for
instance a city, a realm, and an empire are different kinds of state, and indeed
the Church is a sort of state or political community. Hence a nation is one
possible matter of a state, but other matter is not excluded; and every kind
of matter for a state is included in the term ‘a people,’ as Thomas has it (1a 2ae q.105 a.3) when he says: “if foreigners were allowed to
meddle with the affairs of a nation as soon as they settled down in its
midst, many dangers might occur, since the foreigners not yet having the
common good firmly at heart might attempt something hurtful to the people.”
Therefore the material cause of the state is properly the people.
|
Ad primum ergo dicendum quod ius gentium olim,
apud Romanos, significabat ius a praetoribus applicandum ad gentes subditos
civitatis vel imperii Romani (Gilby, p. 110–11). Exinde recepit
significationem iuris quod omnes fere gentes utuntur; sed non necesse est
excludere significationem veterem, quae refert distinctionem inter gentem et
civitatem, sicut civitas Romana superabat gentes multas.
|
Reply to Objection 1: The ‘law of nations’ formerly
meant, among the Romans, the law which the praetors used in governing the
subject nations of the Roman state or empire (Gilby, p. 110–11). From there it later received the meaning of ‘the
law which nearly all nations use’; but it is not necessary to exclude the old
meaning, which does indicate the distinction between nation and state, for
the Roman state subdued many nations.
|
Ad secundum dicendum quod hoc loco Isidorus
loquitur indistincte de institutis gentium vel civitatum, quoniam distinctio
non pertinet ad intellectum iuris gentium in dicendi modo moderno. Sed patet
ex illo Genes., Faciamque te in gentem magnam, quod gens non
identificanda est cum civitate, quoniam civitas Iudaeorum, scilicet regnum,
periit, sed non periit gens Abrahae, scilicet Iudaei; nec peribit usque mundi
consummationem.
|
Reply to Objection 2: In this passage Isidore is
speaking indistinctly about things established either by nations or by
states, since this distinction is not relevant to understanding the law of
nations in the modern sense of the term. But it is evident from that passage
of Genesis, And I will make of thee a great nation, that the nation is
not to be identified with the state, since the Jews’ state, namely the
Kingdom, perished, but Abraham’s nation, namely the Jews, did not perish; nor
will it perish until the end of the world.
|
Monday, 12 August 2019
Nation and State: an article in the style of St Thomas Aquinas
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment