Wednesday, 10 June 2015

Buridan and Oresme on the nature of money

John Buridan, in 1327 rector of the University of Paris and a noted Occamist dialectician, is followed by his disciple Nicholas of Oresme (d. 1384), a theologian at the University of Paris and later Bishop of Lisieux. Oresme has established himself in economic history by his Tractatus de origine, natura, jure, et mutationibus monetarum, a work which directly influenced the monetary policy of Charles V of France; and perhaps more than any other medieval author he has, on account of this work, enjoyed a reputation as an economist.
In his commentary on the Politics of Aristotle, Buridan analyzes money’s nature formally in terms of its four causes. The material cause of money, he says, is some rare material; its efficient cause is the State; its final cause is the needs of men, who must exchange goods; its formal cause is the sign of value upon it. Upon these assumptions, Buridan discusses the morality of the prince altering the legal value, and holds that such alteration may be made if the community as a whole benefited by it, but not otherwise. Significantly, Buridan seems to recognize that the value of money may change even without an official devaluation. He writes, “It is to be known that an alteration in money can happen because sometimes money is called strong, i.e., when its price is increased, and sometimes weak, i.e., when its price is diminished.”
Oresme’s work, following the path of Buridan, is devoted to the nature of money and to the morality of alterations in its value by the prince. Money, Oresme teaches again and again, was invented for the good of the community and belongs to those who have given up natural riches in exchange for it. It should be “as a certain law and certain firm ordinance,” and should never be altered in value unless the community’s necessity authorizes it.

From John T. Noonan, jr., The Scholastic Analysis of Usury (1957), 67–8.